↑ Top


Truncation

This is the Base.Equality.Truncation module of the Agda Universal Algebra Library.

We start with a brief discussion of standard notions of truncation, h-sets (which we just call sets), and the uniqueness of identity types principle. We then prove that a monic function into a set is an embedding. The section concludes with a uniqueness of identity proofs principle for blocks of equivalence relations.

Readers who want to learn more about “proof-relevant mathematics” and other concepts mentioned in this module may wish to consult other sources, such as Section 34 and 35 of Martín Escardó’s notes, or Guillaume Brunerie, Truncations and truncated higher inductive types, or Section 7.1 of the HoTT book.


{-# OPTIONS --without-K --exact-split --safe #-}

module Base.Equality.Truncation where

-- Imports from Agda and the Agda Standard Library  -------------------------------------
open import Agda.Primitive   renaming ( Set to Type )                  using ()
open import Data.Product     renaming ( proj₁ to fst ; proj₂ to snd )  using ( _,_ ; Σ ; Σ-syntax ; _×_ )
open import Function                                                   using ( _∘_ ; id )
open import Level                                                      using ( _⊔_ ; suc ; Level )
open import Relation.Binary  renaming ( Rel to BinRel )                using ( IsEquivalence )
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality as                  using ( _≡_ ; module ≡-Reasoning )
open import Relation.Unary                                             using ( Pred ; _⊆_ )

-- Imports from the Agda Universal Algebra Library --------------------------------------
open import Overture         using ( _⁻¹ ; transport ; ∥_∥ ; _≈_ ; ∣_∣ )
open import Base.Functions    using ( IsInjective )
open import Base.Relations   using ( IsBlock ; Rel ; REL )

private variable α β ρ 𝓥 : Level

The MGS-Quotient module of the Type Topology library defines a uniqueness-of-proofs principle for binary relations. We borrow this and related definitions from Type Topology.

First, a type is a singleton if it has exactly one inhabitant and a subsingleton if it has at most one inhabitant. Representing these concepts are the following types (whose original definitions we import from the MGS-Basic-UF module of Type Topology).


is-center : (A : Type α )  A  Type α
is-center A c = (x : A)  c  x

is-singleton : Type α  Type α
is-singleton A = Σ A (is-center A)

is-prop : Type α  Type α
is-prop A = (x y : A)  x  y

is-prop-valued : {A : Type α}  BinRel A ρ  Type(α  ρ)
is-prop-valued  _≈_ =  x y  is-prop (x  y)

open ≡-Reasoning
singleton-is-prop : {α : Level}(X : Type α)  is-singleton X  is-prop X
singleton-is-prop X (c , φ) x y = x ≡⟨ (φ x)⁻¹  c ≡⟨ φ y  y 

The concept of a fiber of a function is, in the Type Topology library, defined as a Sigma type whose inhabitants represent inverse images of points in the codomain of the given function.


fiber : {A : Type α } {B : Type β } (f : A  B)  B  Type (α  β)
fiber {α}{β}{A} f y = Σ[ x  A ] f x  y

-- A function is called an *equivalence* if all of its fibers are singletons.
is-equiv : {A : Type α } {B : Type β }  (A  B)  Type (α  β)
is-equiv f =  y  is-singleton (fiber f y)

-- An alternative means of postulating function extensionality.
hfunext :   α β  Type (suc (α  β))
hfunext α β = {A : Type α}{B : A  Type β} (f g : (x : A)  B x)  is-equiv (≡.cong-app{f = f}{g})

Thus, if R : Rel A β, then is-subsingleton-valued R is the assertion that for each pair x y : A there can be at most one proof that R x y holds.

Uniqueness of identity proofs

This brief introduction is intended for novices; those already familiar with the concept of truncation and uniqueness of identity proofs may want to skip to the next subsection.

In general, we may have many inhabitants of a given type, hence (via Curry-Howard) many proofs of a given proposition. For instance, suppose we have a type A and an identity relation _≡₀_ on A so that, given two inhabitants of A, say, a b : A, we can form the type a ≡₀ b. Suppose p and q inhabit the type a ≡₀ b; that is, p and q are proofs of a ≡₀ b, in which case we write p q : a ≡₀ b. We might then wonder whether and in what sense are the two proofs p and q the equivalent.

We are asking about an identity type on the identity type ≡₀, and whether there is some inhabitant, say, r of this type; i.e., whether there is a proof r : p ≡ₓ₁ q that the proofs of a ≡₀ b are the same. If such a proof exists for all p q : a ≡₀ b, then the proof of a ≡₀ b is unique; as a property of the types A and ≡₀, this is sometimes called uniqueness of identity proofs (uip).

Now, perhaps we have two proofs, say, r s : p ≡₁ q that the proofs p and q are equivalent. Then of course we wonder whether r ≡₂ s has a proof! But at some level we may decide that the potential to distinguish two proofs of an identity in a meaningful way (so-called proof-relevance) is not useful or desirable. At that point, say, at level k, we would be naturally inclined to assume that there is at most one proof of any identity of the form p ≡ₖ q. This is called truncation (at level k).

Sets

In homotopy type theory, a type A with an identity relation ≡₀ is called a set (or 0-groupoid) if for every pair x y : A there is at most one proof of x ≡₀ y. In other words, the type A, along with it’s equality type ≡₀, form a set if for all x y : A there is at most one proof of x ≡₀ y.

This notion is formalized in the Type Topology library, using the is-subsingleton type that we saw earlier (Base.Functions.Inverses), as follows.


is-set : Type α  Type α
is-set A = is-prop-valued{A = A} _≡_

Thus, the pair (A , ≡₀) forms a set if and only if it satisfies ∀ x y : A → is-subsingleton (x ≡₀ y).

We will also need the function to-Σ-≡, which is part of Escardó’s characterization of equality in Sigma types.


module _ {A : Type α}{B : A  Type β} where

 to-Σ-≡ : {σ τ : Σ[ x  A ] B x}  (Σ[ p  (fst σ  fst τ) ] (transport B p  σ )   τ )  σ  τ
 to-Σ-≡ (≡.refl , ≡.refl) = ≡.refl

Embeddings

The is-embedding type is defined in the MGS-Embeddings module of the Type Topology library in the following way.


is-embedding : {A : Type α}{B : Type β}  (A  B)  Type (α  β)
is-embedding f =  b  is-prop (fiber f b)

singleton-type : {A : Type α}  A  Type α
singleton-type {α}{A} x = Σ[ y  A ] y  x

Thus, is-embedding f asserts that f is a function all of whose fibers are subsingletons. Observe that an embedding is not simply an injective map. However, if we assume that the codomain B has unique identity proofs (UIP), then we can prove that a monic function into B is an embedding. We will do exactly that in the [Base.Relations.Truncation][] module when we take up the topic of sets and the UIP.

Finding a proof that a function is an embedding isn’t always easy, but one approach that is often fairly straightforward is to first prove that the function is invertible and then invoke the invertible-is-embedding theorem from the Type Topology library.


module _ {A : Type α}{B : Type β} where

 invertible : (A  B)  Type (α  β)
 invertible f = Σ[ g  (B  A) ] ((g  f  id) × (f  g  id))

 equiv-is-embedding : (f : A  B)  is-equiv f  is-embedding f
 equiv-is-embedding f i y = singleton-is-prop (fiber f y) (i y)

We will use is-embedding, is-set, and to-Σ-≡ in the next subsection to prove that a monic function into a set is an embedding.

Injective functions are set embeddings

Before moving on to define propositions, we discharge an obligation we mentioned but left unfulfilled in the embeddings section of the Base.Functions.Inverses module. Recall, we described and imported the is-embedding type, and we remarked that an embedding is not simply a monic function. However, if we assume that the codomain is truncated so as to have unique identity proofs (i.e., is a set), then we can prove that any monic function into that codomain will be an embedding. On the other hand, embeddings are always monic, so we will end up with an equivalence.


private variable
 A : Type α
 B : Type β

monic-is-embedding|Set : (f : A  B)  is-set B  IsInjective f  is-embedding f
monic-is-embedding|Set f Bset fmon b (u , fu≡b) (v , fv≡b) = γ
 where
 fuv : f u  f v
 fuv = ≡.trans fu≡b (fv≡b ⁻¹)

 uv : u  v
 uv = fmon fuv

 arg1 : Σ[ p  u  v ] transport  a  f a  b) p fu≡b  fv≡b
 arg1 = uv , Bset (f v) b (transport  a  f a  b) uv fu≡b) fv≡b

 γ : (u , fu≡b)  (v , fv≡b)
 γ = to-Σ-≡ arg1

In stating the previous result, we introduce a new convention to which we will try to adhere. If the antecedent of a theorem includes the assumption that one of the types involved is a set (in the sense defined above), then we add to the name of the theorem the suffix |Set, which calls to mind the standard mathematical notation for the restriction of a function.

Equivalence class truncation

Recall, IsBlock was defined in the Base.Relations.Quotients module as follows:

 IsBlock : {A : Type α}(C : Pred A β){R : Rel A β} → Type(α ⊔ lsuc β)
 IsBlock {A} C {R} = Σ u ꞉ A , C ≡ [ u ] {R}

In the next module we will define a quotient extensionality principle that will require a form of unique identity proofs—specifically, we will assume that for each predicate C : Pred A β there is at most one proof of IsBlock C. We call this proof-irrelevance principle “uniqueness of block identity proofs”, and define it as follows.


blk-uip : (A : Type α)(R : BinRel A ρ )  Type(α  suc ρ)
blk-uip A R =  (C : Pred A _)  is-prop (IsBlock C {R})

It might seem unreasonable to postulate that there is at most one inhabitant of IsBlock C, since equivalence classes typically have multiple members, any one of which could serve as a class representative. However, postulating blk-uip A R is tantamount to collapsing each R-block to a single point, and this is indeed the correct semantic interpretation of the elements of the quotient A / R.

General propositions

This section defines more general truncated predicates which we call continuous propositions and dependent propositions. Recall, above (in the Base.Relations.Continuous module) we defined types called Rel and REL to represent relations of arbitrary arity over arbitrary collections of sorts.

Naturally, we define the corresponding truncated continuous relation type and truncated dependent relation type, the inhabitants of which we will call continuous propositions and dependent propositions, respectively.


module _ {I : Type 𝓥} where

 IsRelProp : {ρ : Level}(A : Type α)  Rel A I{ρ}   Type (𝓥  α  ρ)
 IsRelProp B P =  (b : (I  B))  is-prop (P b)

 RelProp : Type α  (ρ : Level)  Type (𝓥  α  suc ρ)
 RelProp A ρ = Σ[ P  Rel A I{ρ} ] IsRelProp A P

 RelPropExt : Type α  (ρ : Level)  Type (𝓥  α  suc ρ)
 RelPropExt A ρ = {P Q : RelProp A ρ }   P    Q    Q    P   P  Q

 IsRELProp : {ρ : Level} (𝒜 : I  Type α)  REL I 𝒜 {ρ}   Type (𝓥  α  ρ)
 IsRELProp 𝒜 P =  (a : ((i : I)  𝒜 i))  is-prop (P a)

 RELProp : (I  Type α)  (ρ : Level)  Type (𝓥  α  suc ρ)
 RELProp 𝒜 ρ = Σ[ P  REL I 𝒜 {ρ} ] IsRELProp 𝒜 P

 RELPropExt : (I  Type α)  (ρ : Level)  Type (𝓥  α  suc ρ)
 RELPropExt 𝒜 ρ = {P Q : RELProp 𝒜 ρ}   P    Q    Q    P   P  Q

← Base.Equality.Welldefined Base.Equality.Extensionality →